Sunday, November 10, 2019
Language Of Race Essay
(Review of Lawrence Blum, ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ : The Moral Quandary of Race (Ithaca; Cornell University Press, 2002). Theory and Research in Education 1(3), pp. 267-281. ) Lawrence Blumââ¬â¢s book, ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ : The Moral Quandary of Race, is excellent and thought-provoking. It is a model of moral philosophy done well, and, as importantly, done with a purpose. At no point does one wonder, as one does with all too much moral philosophy these days, ââ¬Å"Why does this matter? â⬠Blum makes it clear from the start why we should care about the language and concepts of race and racism, and he does a brilliant job of integrating careful philosophical analysis with contemporary examples, historical explication, and creative thought experiments. Blumââ¬â¢s purpose is basically two-fold: first, to fight against racism and racial injustice by proving that the notion of ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠is both descriptively false and morally inimical and replacing it with the more accurate and useful notion of ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠; and second, to enable and promote productive dialogue about racism and racial inequality, especially between members of different racialized groups. He is explicit only about the second of these aims ââ¬â as he comments in the preface and reiterates in similar terms throughout the book, ââ¬Å"If we agree that racism is so important, donââ¬â¢t we need to know what it is? How can we talk intelligently, especially across racial lines, unless we do? â⬠(p. viii) ââ¬â but the first aim clearly determines the structure and content especially of the second half of the book. In both cases, Blum suggests that language is a key: we can both move forward in the fight against racial injustice and promote cross-racial dialogue about racism and other racial ills, he suggests, if we analyze and clarify what we mean by certain words that are often used too loosely (such as ââ¬Å"racistâ⬠and ââ¬Å"racial 2 discriminationâ⬠); recapture other terms that have inappropriately been divested of moral weight (such as ââ¬Å"racial insensitivityâ⬠and ââ¬Å"prejudiceâ⬠); and abandon the language of ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠altogether because its history of use has made it inherently misleading. This is the primary thrust of the book. In this essay, I will question Blumââ¬â¢s emphasis on language and naming. I will suggest that disagreements about the racial language we use, such as about ââ¬Å"what racism is,â⬠are integral elements of the debate about race and racial injustice, rather than something that can and should be resolved ahead of time. Although Blum characterizes his analysis of racial language as being merely clarificatory, therefore, and designed to advance cross-racial dialogue from the outside, as it were, I will argue that instead he is doing something far different. At best, he is staking a partisan position within the debate itself; at worst, he is cutting it off from the start by building the answers to most of the important questions about racism and racial discrimination into his definitions. In addition to these methodological concerns, I also will query the practical results of implementing the linguistic shifts Blum proposes. I will argue, first, that implementation of ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠-talk will be harder than Blum suggests (even among people who fully accept his arguments and are willing and even eager to abandon ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠in favor of ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠), and second, that it is unlikely to have the social psychological effects Blum predicts. In both of these cases, I will consider teachersââ¬â¢ practices in implementing anti-racist curricula as an important test case, since teachers (along with parents and the media) play a crucial role in shaping the racial language and attitudes of the next generation. i Before I tackle these issues, however, a brief summary of (and a couple of quibbles with) ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ are in order. 3 Blum establishes the moral and conceptual grounding for his project in his first and longest chapter, ââ¬Å"ââ¬ËRacismââ¬â¢: Its Core Meaning. â⬠In this chapter, Blum provides a deft historical, moral, and conceptual analysis of ââ¬Å"racistâ⬠and ââ¬Å"racism. â⬠He is concerned to construct a definition that preserves the strong moral opprobrium that attaches to ââ¬Å"racismâ⬠while avoiding the ââ¬Å"conceptual inflation,â⬠ââ¬Å"moral overload,â⬠and ââ¬Å"categorical driftâ⬠that have come to characterize the terms ââ¬Å"racismâ⬠and ââ¬Å"racistâ⬠ââ¬â i. e. , the indiscriminate application of these terms to a wide variety of categories (such as motives, beliefs, acts, and people) encompassing any and all ââ¬Å"racial illsâ⬠from bigotry to prejudice to racial discomfort, as well as even to non-racial ills such as discrimination based on age, religion, nationality, or physical appearance. By contrast, Blum limits the application of ââ¬Å"racismâ⬠to things stemming specifically from antipathy and/or an inferiorizing attitude toward a racial group. He shows why antipathy and inferiorizing are both sufficient and necessary to his definition ââ¬â for example, one may feel benevolent toward blacks in part because one feels superior to them, but feel antipathetic toward Asians because one assumes they are smarter than oneself; both attitudes would be properly classified as racist, and he argues persuasively that all other examples of racism could fit into one or both of these broad categories. Hence, Blum shows, although racism can be attributed to motives, acts, people, symbols, beliefs, images, epithets, remarks, attitudes, individuals, societies, and institutions (all categories that Blum discusses in detail), each attribution must be independently justified; one cannot just assume that a person who displays a racist symbol, for example, is a racist herself, or even that she necessarily has racist motives. In this respect, Blum is sensitive to the mitigating (although still morally suspect) issues of individual ignorance, unreflective adoption of social norms and behaviors, and unconscious attitudes, any of which may cause an individual to appear but not to be racist, or alternatively to be racist in fact, but to have adopted these racist attitudes 4 subconsciously or even unconsciously. ii Finally, in this chapter Blum gives significant attention not just to racismââ¬â¢s definition but also to its particular moral character. He argues that racism is morally evil not just because it violates ââ¬Å"general moral normsâ⬠such as equality, respect, and good will, but also because of its ââ¬Å"integral tieâ⬠to historical ââ¬Å"race-based systems of oppressionâ⬠that were clearly evil. ââ¬Å"ââ¬Ë Racismââ¬â¢ draws its moral valence from this historical context in two ways. First, the mere fact that these historical systems were based on race provides some of that opprobrium, even if current instances of racism no longer take place in the direct context of, for example, segregation, apartheid, or slavery. . . . [S]econd . . . we continue to live with the legacy of those systemsâ⬠(Blum 2002: 27-8). In chapter 2, Blum asks ââ¬Å"Can Blacks Be Racist? â⬠and answers in the affirmative. No matter what preconditions one places on racism (e. g. that it must be ideologically embedded, or combined with social power), Blum argues, there will be (and are) some black people (as well as members of other minority groups) who meet these criteria and hence must be judged to be racist. Insofar as the denial that blacks can be racist is motivated by a desire to highlight the inherent inequalities among different racist acts and beliefs, however, Blum would agree ââ¬â and argues that ââ¬â there are important ââ¬Å"moral asymmetriesâ⬠in racism. Because of such actsââ¬â¢ ââ¬Å"historical resonanceâ⬠(p. 44), ââ¬Å"greater power to shameâ⬠due to minoritiesââ¬â¢ positional inferiority (p.46), reflection of on-going patterns and prevalence of racism (p. 48), and contribution to maintaining ââ¬Å"systematic racial injusticeâ⬠(p. 49), ââ¬Å"Everything else being equal, greater moral opprobrium rightly attaches to racism by whites against people of color than the reverse. This is the most important moral asymmetry in racismâ⬠(pp. 43-4). Chapter 3 catalogues ââ¬Å"Varieties of Racial Ills,â⬠which are acts or attitudes that deserve some (often substantial) degree of moral condemnation but do not rise to the level of ââ¬Å"racismâ⬠as 5 such. These include racial insensitivity, racial ignorance, racial discomfort, white privilege,exclusionary same-race socializing, and racialism (a term used here to mean ââ¬Å"conferring too much, or inappropriate, importance on peopleââ¬â¢s racial identityâ⬠(p. 59), but which Blum confusingly reuses with a different meaning in chapters 5-9). Chapter 4 then moves into an extremely careful and thoughtful discussion of ââ¬Å"Racial Discrimination and Color Blindness. â⬠He deduces four reasons that discrimination may be wrong: ââ¬Å"(1) it unfairly excludes a qualified individual on the basis of a characteristic irrelevant to the task for which selection is being made; (2) it is done out of prejudice; (3) the prejudice is pervasive and (for that or other reasons) stigmatizing; (4) the discrimination helps to sustain the group whose members are discriminated against in a subordinate positionâ⬠(p. 89). Hence, he argues, the term ââ¬Å"racial discrimination,â⬠which automatically carries with it the implication of moral condemnation, should be confined ââ¬Å"to forms of discrimination involving race that either stem from race-based prejudiced [sic] or that disadvantage an inferiorized or stigmatized groupâ⬠(p. 95). In contrast, he argues, forms of racial differentiation that avoid the four pitfalls listed above may be tolerated or even embraced: for example, racial egalitarianism, which does rely to some extent on racial differentiation but not on discrimination as defined above, is preferable to color blindness. Chapters 5-7 form an undesignated second section of ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ , focusing specifically on the concept, history, and science of ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠in order to debunk it. Blum analyzes the empirical outcomes of thinking in racial terms in chapter 5, ââ¬Å"ââ¬ËRaceââ¬â¢: What We Mean and What We Think We Mean. â⬠He identifies four moral dangers of racial thinking: (1) ââ¬Å"a moral distance among those of different races ââ¬â an intensified consciousness of a ââ¬Ëweââ¬â¢ of one race counterposed to a ââ¬Ëtheyââ¬â¢ of anotherâ⬠(p. 102); (2) the ââ¬Å"imposition of false commonality on all those classified as members of the same raceâ⬠(p. 103); (3) the suggestion of ââ¬Å"an inescapable 6 ââ¬Ëracial fateââ¬â¢Ã¢â¬ (p. 104); and (4) ââ¬Å"associations of superiority and inferiority of valueâ⬠(p. 104). These lead into chapter 6ââ¬â¢s fascinating discussion of ââ¬Å"ââ¬ËRaceââ¬â¢: A Brief History, with Moral Implications,â⬠in which Blum shows the historical contingency and relatively recent vintage of racial thinking, at least in the West. (Although Blumââ¬â¢s language about raceââ¬â¢s recent arrival on the scene is fairly global, his examples are almost entirely confined to ancient Greece and Rome, Europe, and North America; this leaves the reader a bit confused about the intended scope of his historical analysis and claims. ) Finally, chapter 7 boldly asks, ââ¬Å"Do Races Exist? â⬠and marshals a fair amount of scientific evidence (in conjunction with the historical evidence from chapter 6) to answer a resounding ââ¬Å"no. â⬠This outright rejection of race sets up the challenge he confronts in the final two chapters (and unstated third section) of the book: how simultaneously to rid ourselves of the inimical concept of ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠while still promoting the causes of racial justice and equality ââ¬â causes which, as Blum showed in chapter 4, require for their achievement that we name and pay attention (as opposed to blind ourselves) to differences among racial groups. iii In chapter 8, ââ¬Å"Racialized Groups and Social Constructions,â⬠therefore, Blum proposes to replace the concept of ââ¬Å"racesâ⬠with ââ¬Å"racialized groups,â⬠arguing, ââ¬Å"The term ââ¬Ëracialized groupsââ¬â¢ is preferable as a way of acknowledging that some groups have been created by being treated as if they were races, while also acknowledging that ââ¬Ëraceââ¬â¢ in its popular meaning is entirely falseâ⬠(p. 160). Blum further justifies use of the term ââ¬Å"racialized groupsâ⬠in chapter 9, ââ¬Å"Should We Try to Give Up Race? â⬠He argues that racial justice and even a positive sense of racial identity can be promoted by ââ¬Å"racializationâ⬠: ââ¬Å"its recognition supplies a more accurate understanding of the character of the racialized social order, encourages a stronger recognition of commonalities of experience and of political and moral commitments across ââ¬Ëracialââ¬â¢ lines, and, arguably, would in the long run be 7 more politically effective in mitigating racism and racial injustice than would a belief in the reality of raceâ⬠(p. 170). But Blum recognizes that merely transforming our language is not enough; this act will not itself transform the unjust social structures that inform and shape our language: ââ¬Å"In the real world, ridding ourselves of the myth of race can not be severed from the politically more challenging task of changing the structural relationships among racial groupsâ⬠(p. 178). Hence, he concludes by implicitly urging a two-pronged approach to promoting racial justice and equality: altering our language, on the one hand, and engaging in direct social action (especially integrationism), on the other. Critique I find most of Blumââ¬â¢s arguments compelling taken on an individual basis. ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ convinces me that the term ââ¬Å"racismâ⬠should be reserved for race-related, morally egregious beliefs/motives/acts/etc. , that thereââ¬â¢s a wide range of racial ills, that pursuit of racial equality does not amount to racial discrimination, that ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠is a morally inimical concept, and that ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠better captures the historical genesis and conceptual construction we call ââ¬Å"race. â⬠I am not convinced, however, that these arguments taken together satisfy the central articulated aim of the book: namely, to promote cross-racial dialogue about race. This is not, as Iââ¬â¢ve said, because I question his reasoning or his conclusions; rather, I question whether his method, of using substantive moral philosophy, is consonant with this aim. First, some reminders about Blumââ¬â¢s stated aim. As I noted at the beginning of this essay, Blum asks in the preface of ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ , ââ¬Å"If we agree that racism is so important, donââ¬â¢t we need to know what it is? How can we talk intelligently, especially across racial lines, unless we do? . . . . We need to clarify what racism is, to find a basis in history and current use 8 for fixing a definitionâ⬠(p. viii). He reiterates this concern at the beginning of chapter 2: ââ¬Å"My goal of an adequate account of racism is entirely antithetical to race-based attachment to definitions of ââ¬Ëracism. ââ¬â¢ I am seeking an account that will facilitate communication between groups about the character, forms and extent of racism (and other race-related ills). For that we need some agreement on what racism is, and from there we can attempt to settle differences about its extentâ⬠(p. 35). Blumââ¬â¢s aim is clearly to establish a baseline for discussion ââ¬â to foster productive communication by providing moral and conceptual clarification and then to get out of the way in order to allow the now ââ¬Å"intelligentâ⬠and ââ¬Å"facilitatedâ⬠debate to proceed on its own. This is an admirable goal, but I donââ¬â¢t think that ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ achieves it ââ¬â nor do I think that it could achieve it in its current form. This is so for a few reasons. First, it is misleading to suggest that moral philosophy is necessary to fix a definition of ââ¬Å"racism. â⬠So long as thereââ¬â¢s an agreement, or at least mutual comprehension among the interlocutors, as to what each person means in using various terms, then that is sufficient to promote dialogue. For example, if all people accepted that only whites could be racist, then ââ¬Å"cross-racial dialogueâ⬠could proceed on that basis; thereââ¬â¢s no reason that Blumââ¬â¢s definition of racism (which asserts that all people can be racist) is necessary to promote dialogue. Of course, one of Blumââ¬â¢s implicit points is that there isnââ¬â¢t agreement about what racism is, and that such agreement, or even mutual clarification and comprehension, is very unlikely to arise on its own. Rather than revealing a troubling weakness or gap in the discussion, however, this reveal instead the essential nature of the debate about race and racism: namely, that debating the meaning of these terms is part and parcel of debating the things themselves. In other words, fixing a definition is not a neutral act. It is a partisan act. This is because much of the dispute about racism is bound up in how one defines the problem. If individuals unintentionally benefit 9 from the legacy of racism (e. g.via ââ¬Å"white privilegeâ⬠), are they morally responsible in some way? Is it racially discriminatory for an association serving mostly Latino youth to try to hire mostly Latino staff? Is it racist for a small business owner to hire people she ââ¬Å"feels comfortableâ⬠with, if it turns out she tends to feel comfortable only with people from her own racialized group, since thatââ¬â¢s among whom she grew up? These questions lie at the heart of the ââ¬Å"conversation about raceâ⬠; they cannot and should not be settled ahead of time. Thus, Blumââ¬â¢s second methodological mistake is to think that setting a neutral baseline for discussion is even possible. Blumââ¬â¢s approach is inevitably partisan ââ¬â simply in trying to clarify meanings, he takes stances on a number of controversial issues ââ¬â and hence he is within rather than above the fray. This is perfectly appropriate ââ¬â taking and defending particular stances about how we ought to live our lives is what moral philosophy is, or at least should be, about ââ¬â but it is not what Blum professes to be doing. Furthermore, Blumââ¬â¢s approach is at least partly opposed to his stated aim of promoting cross-racial dialogue about race and racism, insofar as to the extent that readers accept Blumââ¬â¢s positions as given, their avenues for debate about race and racism will be cut off rather than expanded. I hope (and expect) instead that readers will be drawn to engage with and debate the arguments themselves, as any good work of social and moral philosophy should inspire people to do; they do not, however, provide a neutral starting point for othersââ¬â¢ conversations. iv My concerns about the match between Blumââ¬â¢s stated objective and the content of his book are irrelevant to my assessment of his arguments or his conclusions, most of which I think are generally on target. I do wonder, however, about the concrete, ââ¬Å"on the groundâ⬠implications of his conclusions, especially but not solely for those responsible for educating the next generation. I will address two especially pressing questions: (1) How would one use the 10 language of ââ¬Å"racialized groupsâ⬠in a way that was clearly distinct from using the language of race, especially in institutional contexts? (2) Is there convincing psychological evidence to support Blumââ¬â¢s claims about the results of redescribing social and identity groups? For example, is there convincing evidence that thinking of oneself as being a member of a socially constructed racialized group has more positive psychological effects than thinking of oneself as a member of a biologically-determined race? These questions raise issues that are significant for assessing the practical import of Blumââ¬â¢s arguments in general; they are also crucial for determining how his conclusions would alter anti-racist curricula and pedagogy in the classroom, which presumably will be central to the realization of Blumââ¬â¢s moral philosophy. First, Blumââ¬â¢s claim that we can combat racism (at least to some extent) by altering our language about race has moral purchase only if there is some way to ââ¬Å"operationalizeâ⬠ââ¬â and especially to institutionalize ââ¬â this linguistic adjustment. Blum seems to acknowledge this, and to be optimistic about its potential: ââ¬Å"Appreciating the difference between race and racialization, and at the same time attempting to do justice to the unreality of race and the reality of racism, may point us toward new ways of thinking and new forms of institutional practiceâ⬠(p. 166). He gives one (and only one) example of how one might adopt ââ¬Å"new forms of institutional practiceâ⬠in relation to the Census, which is a key tool for tracking racial patterns and disparities in society ââ¬â but also hence for seeming to legitimate racial categorization. In response to this dilemma, Blum suggests, ââ¬Å"Were the federal government to encourage a broad understanding that the purposes for which the Census is now explicitly used do not require a commitment to the existence of races in any form, but only to racialized groups, the legitimate discrimination- monitoring function of Census racial categories could be severed from any implication of racialismâ⬠(p. 167). But then frustratingly, Blum gives no specifics about how the Census could 11 do this. Would Blum hope for a statement of disavowal of race? If so, where? Just in the preamble (which already includes a ââ¬Å"baby stepâ⬠in that direction (see p. 227, fn. 11)), which nobody reads? Or in the census itself, which seems impractical since it is intentionally kept as short as possible in order to maximize response rates? Instead of a statement of disavowal, the Census could replace ââ¬Å"What is this personââ¬â¢s race? â⬠(the question currently asked) with ââ¬Å"What is this personââ¬â¢s racialized group? â⬠, and then use quotation marks (or ââ¬Å"scare quotesâ⬠) around terms such as ââ¬Å"black,â⬠ââ¬Å"Spanish/Latino/Hispanicâ⬠(which is currently kept separate from the ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠question), and ââ¬Å"whiteâ⬠to reinforce their constructed status. This is also unsatisfactory, however, for two reasons. First, ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠will likely be either greeted with confusion or treated as a synonym of ââ¬Å"race,â⬠especially in the absence of an explanation of the term; in the latter case, it is likely to end up acquiring the separatist, hierarchical, and essentialist connotations or ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠(just like ââ¬Å"disabledâ⬠and even ââ¬Å"differently abledâ⬠acquired those of the maligned term ââ¬Å"handicappedâ⬠they were designed to replace). Second, many of the choices given are not (yet) ââ¬Å"racialized groups,â⬠at least not in the United States, but are nationalities: Samoan, Filipino, Native Hawaiian, Asian Indian, Japanese. Should these terms all be in scare quotes? I would think not ââ¬â but then how would one deal with the presence of scare quotes some places and their absence others? One could add ââ¬Å"nationality and/or ethnicityâ⬠to the ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠question, and then surround everything with quotation marks ââ¬â but this then gets cumbersome, to say the least, and is likely to raise other dilemmas. As the Census example shows, institutionalizing ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠language is hard in print, particularly when it comes to naming and labeling the racialized groups themselves (ââ¬Å"black,â⬠ââ¬Å"white,â⬠ââ¬Å"Vietnamese,â⬠ââ¬Å"Native Americanâ⬠). It is substantially harder in conversation, 12 such as in the oral give-and-take of a classroom. Consider Ellen, a teacher of ten and eleven year-olds, who is eager to incorporate anti-racist education into her teaching. Ellen reads ââ¬Å"Iââ¬â¢m Not a Racist, Butâ⬠¦Ã¢â¬ over the winter holiday and then sits down to revise her January lesson plans, which include a unit on non-violent protest designed both to fit into the schoolââ¬â¢s conflict resolution initiative and to lead up to the celebration of Martin Luther King, Jr. ââ¬â¢s birthday. As she reads over her plans, she quickly inserts a mini-lesson on ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠at the beginning of the unit and converts ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠to ââ¬Å"racialized groupâ⬠throughout the unit. She adds in a two-day lesson called ââ¬Å"What is Racism? â⬠, and develops an interactive group activity for near the end of the unit designed to help students decide when itââ¬â¢s okay to refer to or take someoneââ¬â¢s racialized group membership into account and when itââ¬â¢s not. Reviewing her social studies lessons on Ghandi, Martin Luther King, Jr. , and the March on Washington, D. C. , she is pleased. She also thinks her English lesson on an excerpt of Kingââ¬â¢s Letter from Birmingham Jail will prove challenging but inspiring to her students. But then Ellen suddenly gets worried. Throughout her lessons are references to blacks, whites, Indians, British, Hindus, Christians, Jews. Which of these are racialized groups and which are not? How can she help her students figure out the difference? How can she talk about ââ¬Å"blacksâ⬠and ââ¬Å"whitesâ⬠to her class without her students falling back into racial thinking? She can hand-signal scare quotes each time, but will that just turn into a joke among the students? And which groups would she use the hand signals for? All of these concerns are predicated on the conclusion that language matters ââ¬â that it influences how we think, reason, behave, and interact with one another. This brings us to my second question about implications of Blumââ¬â¢s conclusions: is there social psychological evidence in favor of them? Throughout the book, Blum clearly operates on the assumption that if people recognize the socially constructed, rather than biologically inherent, nature of racialized groups, 13 then they will better be able to fight against the ââ¬Å"hierarchicalâ⬠and ââ¬Å"inegalitarianâ⬠(p. 107) assumptions inherent in racial thinking. This is partly because racial identity then becomes in some way a matter of choice. ââ¬Å"Whether a group is racialized is a matter of its treatment by the larger society. Whether the group takes on a self-identity as a race is a different matterâ⬠(p. 148). In recognizing their racialized treatment, rather than believing themselves defined by an immutable racial identity, individuals who are members of racialized groups can decide how to respond. Will they embrace their racialized identity, as those do who proudly join the Asian- American club, volunteer with La Raza, or wear t-shirts proclaiming ââ¬Å"Itââ¬â¢s a BLACK thing ââ¬â you wouldnââ¬â¢t understandâ⬠or ââ¬Å"Hot Latina Mamaâ⬠? Will they reject it, declaring ââ¬Å"thatââ¬â¢s not who I amâ⬠and/or trying to assimilate? Or will they try to subvert it in some way, say by reclaiming the term ââ¬Å"niggerâ⬠(or ââ¬Å"queerâ⬠in the [non-racial] case of gays) and defiantly using it as a term of affection for others inside the group? By choosing the extent and nature of their racial identities, Blum seems implicitly to be arguing, individuals and groups are empowered; whether they choose to appropriate, reject, or subvert the characterizations thrust upon them by racializing others, the very act of choosing liberates them from the racialist (and racist) assumptions of innate difference, inferiority, and/or stigma. Two substantial bodies of work in social psychology, however, cast serious doubt on this claim. The first is system justification theory ââ¬â the theory that ââ¬Å"psychological processes contribut[e] to the preservation of existing social arrangements even at the expense of personal and group interestâ⬠(Jost and Banaji 1994: 1). The second is the notion of ââ¬Å"stereotype threatâ⬠ââ¬â the idea that in certain situations (those posing ââ¬Å"stereotype threatâ⬠), members of stigmatized groups worry about confirming a negative stereotype about their group through their performance on a task, and then, precisely because of this anxiety, end up performing worse on 14 the task than they otherwise would (and than others do) ââ¬â thus paradoxically performing true to negative stereotype (see Steele and Aronson 1995; Steele 1997). I will address each in turn. According to system justification theory, people implicitly support the status quo, including hierarchy differences between low- and high-status groups, even when they are members of low-status groups, and even when they reject the distinctions on a conscious level. Thus, in studies done under both ââ¬Å"authenticâ⬠and experimental conditions, women ask for lower wages than men do for the same work (or they work 25 percent longer than men if offered the same wage (Cite forthcoming)); individuals rate even initially unwanted outcomes (such as tuition increases, or a member of the opposing political party winning an election) more desirable the more likely they are to occur (Kay et al.2002); And they rationalize the legitimacy of existing inequalities (e. g. , if told that graduates of University B earn more on average than University A graduates, University A students will rate University B students as being smarter and better writers than they; if told the opposite, however, then University A students will express the opposite prejudice and rate themselves higher (cite forthcoming)). Even individuals who explicitly articulate egalitarian beliefs tend to demonstrate moderate to strong implicit attitudinal biases toward higher-status groups (whites, young people, men); this is true regardless of the individualââ¬â¢s own group membership(s) (Greenwald and Banaji 1995; Banaji 2001). In other words, individuals internalize prejudice, discrimination, racism, and/or oppression (Jost and Banaji 1994; Jost et al. 2002; Kay et al. 2002). ââ¬Å"[M]embers of disadvantaged groups internalize negative stereotypes and evaluations of their own group, to at least some degreeâ⬠(Jost et. al. 2002: 598). Thus, even if people know that they are members of a group that is treated (merely) as if ââ¬Å"there were inherent and immutable differences between them; as if certain somatic characteristics marked the presence of significant characteristics of mind, emotion, and 15 character; and as if some were of greater worth than othersâ⬠(Blum 2002: 147), they are still likely to believe, subconsciously at least, that these are accurate assessments of their group membership. It takes a great deal of inner strength to stand up to stigma, discrimination, and prejudice. Even those who consciously reject racialist presumptions may respond differently subconsciously. This may be because of internalized oppression, as discussed above. But it may also be a result of rational adjustments in motivation or expectations. Knowing that one ââ¬Å"is discriminated against, stigmatized, or inherits a history of racialâ⬠disadvantage (p. 177) may very well (and rationally) lead one to adopt a presumption of disadvantage ââ¬â a belief that oneââ¬â¢s effort will not be rewarded because of on-going discrimination and racism, and hence a reduction in effort, motivation, and/or aspirations. There is clear evidence of both effort reduction (Stone 2002) and aspiration reduction even among people who consciously reject stereotypes, such as women who profess a liking for mathematics (Nosek et al. 2002). This lowering of expectations is clearly compounded if individuals accept, whether implicitly or explicitly, the idea that they really are inferior in some way (as system justification theory suggests). Furthermore, as Claude Steeleââ¬â¢s acclaimed work on ââ¬Å"stereotype threatâ⬠shows, there are significant psychological and performative costs even simply in knowing that one is a member of a group that is perceived in a negative light. For example, research over the past few years has consistently shown that black students do worse on verbal tests if told the test is a measure of ability than they do if they are told the test is non-diagnostic (Steele 1997); the same is true for womenââ¬â¢s performance on math tests (Keller 2002). Similarly, white students do worse than controls on tests of athletic skills if told that the their performance will indicate their ââ¬Å"natural athletic ability,â⬠but black students do worse if told their performance indicates their ââ¬Å"sports 16 intelligenceâ⬠(Stone, et. al. 1999). This response to ââ¬Å"stereotype threatâ⬠is evident even among very young children (ages six to ten): children above seven years old demonstrate high levels of stereotype consciousness (awareness of othersââ¬â¢ stereotypes about various groups), and children who are members of stigmatized groups perform worse when they think they are being measured along stereotypic lines than they do on the exact same test when their stereotype awareness (and hence sense of stereotype threat) is not activated (McKown 2002). These results pose a serious challenge, I believe, to Blumââ¬â¢s claims about the practical import of his moral philosophy. Although it is true that this research has all been done under conditions of ââ¬Å"raceâ⬠rather than ââ¬Å"racialized groupsâ⬠being salient (insofar as ââ¬Å"racialized groupsâ⬠has not become a popular or widespread term), it strikes me as being highly unl. Ã
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.